TY - CHAP
T1 - An epistemic framework for scientific reasoning in informal contexts
AU - Yang, Fang Ying
AU - Tsai, Chin Chung
N1 - Publisher Copyright:
© Cambridge University Press 2010.
PY - 2010/1/1
Y1 - 2010/1/1
N2 - Introduction In the science education community, there is a growing consensus that in addition to conceptual knowledge, we need to introduce learners to another important facet of science, that is, how we create new knowledge. In other words, students should be better educated in the use of certain established ways of thinking in science (e.g., Duschl, 1990; Lawson., 2000). The “certain established ways of thinking in science” are commonly referred to as scientific reasoning, which is portrayed by philosophers of science as a process of argumentation (Giere, 1991; Seigel, 1988; Toulmin, 1958), because it involves the evaluation of evidence to support a theory or claim. In schools, scientific reasoning is usually presented in domain-specific contexts such as physics, chemistry, life sciences, and so forth. Nevertheless, as Seigel (1988) has noted, the commitment to evidence is an imperative trait of rational reasoning in many disciplines, although the form it takes may vary with the disciplines. Even in everyday situations, testing of the possibilities with accountable evidence or reasons and searching for possibilities are critical for decision-making (Baron 1988; Kuhn, 1991; Lawson., 2000; Perkins and Salman, 1989). Hence, although scientific reasoning is often discussed within specific knowledge domains, as Kuhn (1993) pointed out, it represents a domain-independent mode of argumentative reasoning. The development of scientific reasoning has been widely discussed in psychological research (Zimmerman, 2000). Nevertheless, most studies are placed in domain-specific contexts and deal with well-structured problems with only a few exceptions (Kuhn, 1991, 1993).
AB - Introduction In the science education community, there is a growing consensus that in addition to conceptual knowledge, we need to introduce learners to another important facet of science, that is, how we create new knowledge. In other words, students should be better educated in the use of certain established ways of thinking in science (e.g., Duschl, 1990; Lawson., 2000). The “certain established ways of thinking in science” are commonly referred to as scientific reasoning, which is portrayed by philosophers of science as a process of argumentation (Giere, 1991; Seigel, 1988; Toulmin, 1958), because it involves the evaluation of evidence to support a theory or claim. In schools, scientific reasoning is usually presented in domain-specific contexts such as physics, chemistry, life sciences, and so forth. Nevertheless, as Seigel (1988) has noted, the commitment to evidence is an imperative trait of rational reasoning in many disciplines, although the form it takes may vary with the disciplines. Even in everyday situations, testing of the possibilities with accountable evidence or reasons and searching for possibilities are critical for decision-making (Baron 1988; Kuhn, 1991; Lawson., 2000; Perkins and Salman, 1989). Hence, although scientific reasoning is often discussed within specific knowledge domains, as Kuhn (1993) pointed out, it represents a domain-independent mode of argumentative reasoning. The development of scientific reasoning has been widely discussed in psychological research (Zimmerman, 2000). Nevertheless, most studies are placed in domain-specific contexts and deal with well-structured problems with only a few exceptions (Kuhn, 1991, 1993).
UR - http://www.scopus.com/inward/record.url?scp=84876717889&partnerID=8YFLogxK
UR - http://www.scopus.com/inward/citedby.url?scp=84876717889&partnerID=8YFLogxK
U2 - 10.1017/CBO9780511691904.005
DO - 10.1017/CBO9780511691904.005
M3 - Chapter
AN - SCOPUS:84876717889
SN - 9780521883559
SP - 124
EP - 162
BT - Personal Epistemology in the Classroom
PB - Cambridge University Press
ER -